Page 161 of 162
56 (return)
[ NOTE DDD, p. 465. This
protestation is so remarkable, that it may not be improper to give it in
its own words. “The commons now assembled in parliament, being justly
occasioned thereunto, concerning sundry liberties, franchises, and
privileges of parliament, amongst others here mentioned, do make this
protestation following: That the liberties, franchises, and jurisdictions
of parliament are the ancient and undoubted birthright and inheritance of
the subjects of England; and that the urgent and arduous affairs
concerning the king, state, and defence of the realm and of the church of
England, and the maintenance and making of laws, and redress of mischiefs
and grievances which daily happen within this realm, are proper subjects
and matter of counsel and debate in parliament; and that, in the handling
and proceeding of those businesses, every member of the house of
parliament hath, and of right ought to have, freedom of speech to
propound, treat, reason, and bring to conclusion the same; and that the
commons in parliament have like liberty and freedom to treat of these
matters, in such order as in their judgment shall seem fittest; and that
every member of the said house hath like freedom from all impeachment,
imprisonment, and molestation, (other than by censure of the house
itself,) for or concerning any speaking, reasoning, or declaring of any
matter or matters touching the parliament or parliament business. And that
if any of the said members be complained of or questioned for any thing
done or said in parliament, the same is to be shown to the king by the
advice and assent of all the commons assembled in parliament, before the
king give credence to any private information.” Franklyn, p. 65. Rush,
vol. i p. 53. Kennet, p. 747. Coke, p. 77.]
57 (return)
[ NOTE EEE, p. 434. The
moment the prince embarked at St. Andero’s, he said to those about him,
that it was folly in the Spaniards to use him so ill, and allow him to
depart: a proof that the duke had made him believe they were insincere in
the affair of the marriage and the Palatinate; for as to his reception in
other respects, it had been altogether unexceptionable. Besides, had not
the prince believed the Spaniards to be insincere, he had no reason to
quarrel with them, though Bucking-* *ham had. It appears, therefore, that
Charles himself must have been deceived. The multiplied delays of the
dispensation, though they arose from accident, afforded Buckingham a
plausible pretext for charging the Spaniards with insincerity.]
58 (return)
[ NOTE FFF, p. 486. Among
other particulars, he mentions a sum of eighty thousand pounds borrowed
from the king of Denmark. In a former speech to the parliament, he told
them that he had expended five hundred thousand pounds in the cause of the
palatine, besides the voluntary contributions given him by the people. See
Franklyn, p. 50. But what is more extraordinary, the treasurer, in order
to show his own good services, boasts to the parliament, that by his
contrivance sixty thousand pounds had been saved in the article of
exchange in the sums remitted to the palatine. This seems a great sum; nor
is it easy to conceive whence the king could procure such vast sums as
would require a sum so considerable to be paid in exchange. From the
whole, however, it appears, that the king had been far from neglecting the
interests of his daughter and son-in-law, and had even gone far beyond
what his narrow revenue could afford.]
59 (return)
[ NOTE GGG, p. 486. How
little this principle had prevailed during any former period of the
English government, particularly during the last reign, which was
certainly not so perfect a model of liberty as most writers would
represent it, will easily appear from many passages in the history of that
reign. But the ideas of men were much changed during about twenty years of
a gentle and peaceful administration. The commons, though James of himself
had recalled all patents of monopolies, were not contented without a law
against them, and a declaratory law too; which was gaining a great point,
and establishing principles very favorable to liberty: but they were
extremely grateful when Elizabeth, upon petition, (after having once
refused their requests,) recalled a few of the most oppressive patents,
and employed some soothing expressions towards them.
The
parliament had surely reason, when they confessed, in the seventh of
James, that he allowed them more freedom of debate than ever was indulged
by any of his predecessors. His indulgence in this particular, joined to
his easy temper, was probably one cause of the great power assumed by the
commons. Monsieur de la Boderie, in his despatches, (vol. i. p. 449,)
mentions the liberty of speech in the house of commons as a new practice.]
60 (return)
[ NOTE HHH, p. 491. Rymer,
tom. xviii. p. 224. It is certain that the young prince of Wales,
afterwards Charles II., had Protestant governors from his early infancy;
first the earl of Newcastle, then the marquis of Hertford. The king, in
his memorial to foreign churches after the commencement of the civil wars,
insists on his care in educating his children in the Protestant religion,
as a proof that he was nowise inclined to the Catholic, Rush. vol. v. p.
752. It can scarcely, therefore, be questioned, but this article, which
has so odd an appearance, was inserted only to amuse the pope, and was
never intended by either party to be executed.]
61 (return)
[ NOTE III, p. 499.
“Monarchies,” according to Sir Walter Raleigh, “are of two sorts touching
their power or authority, viz. 1. Entire, where the whole power of
ordering all state matters, both in peace and war, doth by law and custom
appertain to the prince, as in the English kingdom; where the prince hath
the power to make laws, league, and war, to create magistrates, to pardon
life, of appeal, etc. Though to give a contentment to the other degrees,
they have a suffrage in making laws, yet ever subject to the prince’s
pleasure and negative will. 2. Limited or restrained, that hath no full
power in all the points and matters of state, as the military king that
hath not the sovereignty in time of peace, as the making of laws, etc.,
but in war only, as the Polonian king.” Maxims of State.
And a
little after: “In every just state, some part of the government is, or
ought to be, imparted to the people, as in a kingdom, a voice and suffrage
in making laws; and sometimes also of levying of arms, (if the charge be
great, and the prince forced to borrow help of his subjects,) the matter
rightly may be propounded to a parliament, that the tax may seem to have
proceeded from themselves. So consultations and some proceedings in
judicial matters may in part be referred to them. The reason, lest, seeing
themselves to be in no number nor of reckoning, they mislike the state or
government.” This way of reasoning differs little from that of King James,
who considered the privileges of the parliament as matters of grace and
indulgence, more than of inheritance. It is remarkable that Raleigh was
thought to lean towards the Puritanical party, notwithstanding these
positions. But ideas of government change much in different times.
Raleigh’s sentiments on this head are still more openly expressed in his
Prerogatives of Parliaments, a work not published till after his death. It
is a dialogue between a courtier, or counsellor, and a country justice of
peace, who represents the patriot party, and defends the highest notion of
liberty which the principles of that age would bear. Here is a passage of
it: “Counsellor. That which is done by the king, with the advice of his
private or privy council, is done by the king’s absolute power. Justice.
And by whose power is it done in parliament but by the king’s absolute
power? Mistake it not, my lord: the three estates do but advise as the
privy council doth; which advice if the king embrace, it becomes the
king’s own act in the one, and the king’s law in the other,” etc.
The earl of Clare, in a private letter to his son-in-law, Sir Thomas
Wentworth, afterwards earl of Strafford, thus expresses himself “We live
under a prerogative government, where book law submits to lex loquens.” He
spoke from his own and all his ancestors experience. There was no single
instance of power which a king of England might not at that time exert, on
pretence of necessity or expediency: the continuance alone, or frequent
repetition of arbitrary administration, might prove dangerous, for want of
force to support it. It is remarkable, that this letter of the earl of
Clare was written in the first year of Charles’s reign; and consequently
must be meant of the general genius of the government, not the spirit or
temper of the monarch. See Strafford’s Letters, vol. i. p. 32. From
another letter in the same collection, (vol. i. p. 10,) it appears that
the council sometimes assumed the power of forbidding persons disagreeable
to the court to stand in the elections. This authority they could exert in
some instances; but we are not thence to inter, that they could shut the
door of that house to every one who was not acceptable to them. The genius
of the ancient government reposed more trust in the king, than to
entertain any such suspicion; and it allowed scattered instances of such a
kind, as would have been totally destructive of the constitution, had they
been continued without interruption.
I have not met with any
English writer in that age who speaks of England as a limited monarchy,
but as an absolute one, where the people have many privileges. That is no
contradiction. In all European monarchies the people have privileges; but
whether dependent or independent on the will of the monarch, is a question
that in most governments it is better to forbear. Surely that question was
not determined before the age of James. The rising spirit of the
parliament, together with that king’s love of general, speculative
principles, brought it from its obscurity, and made it be commonly
canvassed. The strongest testimony that I remember from a writer of
James’s age in favor of English liberty, is in Cardinal Bentivoglio, a
foreigner, who mentions the English government as similar to that of the
Low Country provinces under their princes, rather than to that of France
or Spain. Englishmen were not so sensible that their prince was limited,
because they were sensible that no individual had any security against a
stretch of prerogative: but foreigners, by comparison, could perceive that
these stretches were at that time, from custom or other causes, less
frequent in England than in other monarchies. Philip de Comines, too,
remarked the English constitution to be more popular in his time than that
of France. But in a paper written by a patriot in 1627, it is remarked,
that the freedom of speech in parliament had been lost in England since
the days of Comines. Franklyn, p. 238. Here is a stanza of Malherbe’s Ode
to Mary de Medicis, the queen regent, written in 1614.
Entre
les rois qui cet age Doit son principal ornement, Ceux de la Tamise et
du Tage Font louer leur gouvernement: Mais en de si calmes provinces, O
le peuple adore les princes, Et met au gr le plus haut L’honneur du
sceptre lgitime, Sauroit-on excuser le crime De ne regner pas comme il
faut.
The English, as well as the Spaniards, are here pointed
out as much more obedient subjects than the French, and much more
tractable and submissive to their princes. Though this passage be taken
from a poet, every man of judgment will allow its authority to be
decisive. The character of a national government cannot be unknown in
Europe; though it changes sometimes very suddenly. Machiavel, in his
Dissertations on Livy, says repeatedly, that France was the most legal and
most popular monarchy then in Europe.]