Page 158 of 159
20 (return)
[ NOTE T, p. 380. The
imputation of insincerity on Charles I., like most party clamors, is
difficult to be removed; though it may not here be improper to say
something with regard to it. I shall first remark, that this imputation
seems to be of a later growth than his own age; and that even his enemies,
though they loaded him with many calumnies, did not insist on this
accusation. Ludlow, I think, is almost the only parliamentarian who
imputes that vice to him; and how passionate a writer he is, must be
obvious to every one. Neither Clarendon nor any other of the royalists
ever justify him from insincerity, as not supposing that he had ever been
accused of it. In the second place, his deportment and character in common
life was free from that vice. He was reserved, distant, stately; cold in
his address, plain in his discourse, inflexible in his principles; wide of
the caressing, insinuating manners of his son, or the professing,
talkative humor of his father. The imputation of insincerity must be
grounded on some of his public actions, which we are therefore in the
third place to examine. The following are the only instances which I find
cited to confirm that accusation. 1. His vouching Buckingham’s narrative
of the transactions in Spain. But it is evident that Charles himself was
deceived: why otherwise did he quarrel with Spain? The following is a
passage of a letter from Lord Kensington, ambassador in France, to the
duke of Buckingham Cabbala p. 318. “But his highness (the prince) had
observed as great a weakness and folly as that, in that after they (the
Spaniards) had used him so ill, they would suffer him to depart, which was
one of the first speeches he uttered after he came into the ship. But did
he say so? said the queen (of France.) Yes, madam, I will assure you,
quoth I, from the witness of mine own ears. She smiled, and replied,
Indeed, I heard he was used ill. So he was, answered I, but not in his
entertainment; for that was as splendid as that country could afford it;
but in their frivolous delays, and in the unreasonable conditions which
they propounded and pressed, upon the advantage they had of his princely
person.” 2. Bishop Burnet, in his History of the House of Hamilton, (p.
154.) has preserved a letter of the king’s to the Scottish bishops, in
which he desires them not to be present at the parliament, where they
would be forced to ratify the abolition of their own order. “For,” adds
the king, “we do hereby assure you, that it shall be still one of our
chiefest studies how to rectify and establish the government of that
church aright, and to repair your losses, which we desire you to be most
confident of.” And in another place, “You may rest secure, that though
perhaps we may give way for the present to that which will be prejudicial
both to the church and our own government, yet we shall not leave thinking
in time how to remedy both.” But does the king say that he will
arbitrarily revoke his concessions? Does not candor require us rather to
suppose, that he hoped his authority would so far recover as to enable him
to obtain the national consent to reestablish Episcopacy, which he
believed so material a part of religion as well as of government? It is
not easy indeed to think how he could hope to effect this purpose in any
other way than his father had taken, that is, by consent of parliament. 3.
There is a passage in Lord Clarendon, where it is said, that the king
assented the more easily to the bill which excluded the bishops from the
house of peers, because he thought that that law, being enacted by force,
could not be valid. But the king certainly reasoned right in that
conclusion. Three fourths of the temporal peers were at that time banished
by the violence of the populace. Twelve bishops were unjustly thrown into
the Tower by the commons. Great numbers of the commons themselves were
kept away by fear or violence. The king himself was chased from London. If
all this be not force, there is no such thing. But this scruple of the
king’s affects only the bishops’ bill, and that against pressing. The
other constitutional laws had passed without the least appearance of
violence, as did indeed all the bills passed during the first year, except
Strafford’s attainder, which could not be recalled. The parliament,
therefore, even if they had known the king’s sentiments in this
particular, could not, on that account, have had any just foundation of
jealousy. 4. The king’s letter intercepted at Naseby has been the source
of much clamor. We have spoken of it already in chapter lviii. Nothing is
more usual in all public transactions than such distinctions. Alter the
death of Charles II. of Spain, King William’s ambassadors gave the duke of
Anjou the title of King of Spain; yet at that very time, King William was
secretly forming alliances to dethrone him and soon after he refused him
that title, and insisted (as he had reason) that he had not acknowledged
his right. Yet King William justly passes for a very sincere prince; and
this transaction is not regarded as any objection to his character in that
particular. In all the negotiations at the peace of Ryswic, the French
ambassadors always addressed King William as king of England; yet it was
made an express article of the treaty, that the French king should
acknowledge him as such. Such a palpable difference is there between
giving a title to a prince, and positively recognizing his right to it. I
may add, that Charles, when he asserted that protestation in the council
books before his council, surely thought he had reason to justify his
conduct. There were too many men of honor in that company to avow a
palpable cheat. To which we may subjoin, that, if men were as much
disposed to judge of this prince’s actions with candor as severity, this
precaution of entering a protest in his council books might rather pass
for a proof of scrupulous honor; lest he should afterwards be reproached
with breach of his word, when he should think proper again to declare the
assembly at Westminster no parliament. 5. The denying of his commission to
Glamorgan is another instance which has been cited. This matter has been
already treated in a footnote to chapter lviii. That transaction was
entirely innocent. Even if the king had given a commission to Glamorgan to
conclude that treaty, and had ratified it, will any reasonable man, in our
age, think it strange that, in order to save his own life, his crown, his
family, his friends, and his party, he should make a treaty with Papists,
and grant them very large concessions for their religion? 6. There is
another of the king’s intercepted letters to the queen commonly mentioned;
where, it is pretended, he talked of raising and then destroying Cromwell.
But that story stands on no manner of foundation, as we have observed in a
preceding footnote to this chapter. In a word, the parliament, after the
commencement of their violences, and still more after beginning the civil
war, had reason for their scruples and jealousies, founded on the very
nature of their situation, and on the general propensity of the human
mind; not on any fault of the king’s character, who was candid, sincere,
upright; as much as any man whom we meet with in history. Perhaps it would
be difficult to find another character so unexceptionable in this
particular.
As to the other circumstances of Charles’s
character chiefly exclaimed against, namely, his arbitrary principles in
government, one may venture to assert, that the greatest enemies of this
prince will not find, in the long line of his predecessors, from the
conquest to his time, any one king, except perhaps his father, whose
administration was not more arbitrary and less legal, or whose conduct
could have been recommended to him, by the popular party themselves, as a
model, in this particular, for his government. Nor is it sufficient to
say, that example and precedent can never authorize vices. Examples and
precedents, uniform and ancient, can surely fix the nature of any
constitution, and the limits of any form of government. There is indeed no
other principle by which those landmarks or boundaries can be settled.
What a paradox in human affairs, that Henry VIII. should have
been almost adored in his lifetime, and his memory be respected; while
Charles I. should, by the same people, at no greater distance than a
century, have been led to a public and ignominious execution, and his name
be ever after pursued by falsehood and by obloquy!
Even at
present, an historian, who, prompted by his courageous generosity, should
venture, though from the most authentic and undisputed facts, to vindicate
the fame of that prince, would be sure to meet with such treatment as
would discourage even the boldest from so dangerous, however splendid an
enterprise.]